Schmithausen on the Yogaacaara's aalayavij~naana teaching, wherein
Schmithausen disagreed with a Japanese scholar, H. Hakamaya, who insisted that Asa^nga was
the compiler of the entire encyclopedic Yogaacaarabhuumi. Here Schmithausen thought to
counter Hakamaya's position by noting the use of thescripture Sa.mdhinirmocana in some
parts or the larger work and not in other parts. About that scripture, Schmithausen
concluded: "Therefore, the Sa.mdhinirmocana-suutra, at least the portions concerned
with the new kind of vij~naana distinguished from the ordinary six, was most probably
composed before the Vini'scayasa.mgraha.nii but after the Basic Section of the
Yogaacaarabhuumi."(4) It happens that a Japanese student, H. S. Sakuma, completed a
dissertation at Hamburg, approved by Schmithausen, wherein he presented (in German) this
very position stated above hence copied. In my review of this published work I pointed
out: "One may refer in my Analysis of the 'Sraavakabhuumi Manuscript, (5) 110-11, to
a passage on the three doors of vipa'syanaa. This passage is virtually the same as is
found in the Sa.mdhinirmocanasuutra, ch. 8, sect. 10. This is a proof that the author of
the Sraavakabhuumi agreed to be the oldest part of what Sakuma calls Maulii Bhuumi [the
'Basic Section] had available and used the Sa.mdhinirmocanasuutra."(6)This, then, is
an example of where the copying turned out to be incorrect, and was defended against by
calling attention to what the Yogaacaara itself says about the matter.
These two examples should clarify what is meant by misrepresentations
(or possible ones) that are defended against not really by the present writer s an
independent thinker, but rather by the Yogaacaara system itself being brought to bear upon
the alleged misrepresentation. This essay continues with two main sections below:
(1) The Position of the Yogaacaarins and (2) Clarification of the
Position.
The Position of the Yogaacaarins
Here I present four topics:
- Vasubandhu and an early scripture;
- about cittamaatra;
- about aalayavij~naana; and
- about three lak.sa.na.
Vasubandhu and an Early Scripture. Some authors treat the Yogaacaara
system as though it were an invention of the founders, notably the brothers Asa^nga and
Vasubandhu. To suggest otherwise, may we notice that Bhikkhu ~Naa.nananda has put out a
boolet on the Kaa.lakaaraama Sutta.(7) This scripture is in the A^nguttara-Nikaaya, Book
of Fours, where it was translated by Woodward,(8) who noticed certain textual
difficulties. The Bhikkhu used some other editions and studied Buddhaghosa's commentary on
every word for his English rendition, wherein he obviously uses Woodward's words whenever
possible. In the following I have substituted my rendition 'gods and humans' and subdivide
the translation with brief, bracketed remarks.
The Kaa.lakaaraama Sutta. [The Setting.] At one time the Exalted One
was staying in Saaketa in Kaa.laka's monastery. There the Exalted One addressed the monks,
saying: "Monks." "Revered Sir," replied those monks in assent. [As a
Vedic or Greek god would talk, declaring omniscience,] the Exalted One said: "Monks,
whatsoever in the world with its gods, Maaras and Brahmas, among the progeny consisting of
recluses and brahmins, gods and humans whatsoever is seen, heard, sensed (sensations
arising from taste, touch and smell), cognized, attained, sought after and pondered over
by the mind all that do I know. Monks, whatsoever in the world... of gods and humans,
whatsoever is seen,... by the mind, that have I fully understood; all that is known to the
Tathaagata, but the Tathaagata has not taken his stand upon it. [Now he denies
alternatives to be construed as four in number, because the scripture is in the Book of
Fours.] If I were to say: 'Monks, whatsoever in the world... of... gods and humans
whatsoever is seen... by the mind all that I do not know' it would be a falsehood in me.
If I were to say: 'I both know it and know it not' that too would be a falsehood in me. If
I were to say: 'I neither know it nor am ignorant of itit would be a fault in me.
[The Buddha now declares how one uses the senses while avoiding the 'apprehender' and the
'apprehended'.] Thus, monks, a Tathaagata does not conceive of a visible thing as apart
from sight; he does not conceive of an 'unseen', he does not conceive of a
'thing-worth-seeing', he does not conceive about a seer. He does not conceive of an
audible thing as apart from hearing; he does not conceive of 'an unheard', he does not
conceive of a 'thing-worth-hearing', he does not conceive about a hearer. He does not
conceive of a thing to be sensed as apart from sensation; he does not conceive of a
'thing-worth-sensing', he does not conceive about one who senses. He does not conceive of
a cognizable thing as apart from cognition; he does not conceive of a
'thing-worth-cognizing', he does not conceive about one who cognizes. Thus, monks, the
Tathaagata, being such-like in regard to all phenomena seen, heard, sensed, and cognized,
is 'Such'. Moreover, than he who is 'Such', there is none other greater or more excellent,
I declare." [Now verses on how ordinary persons use their senses, sometimes called
'the fantasy of normalcy'.]
Whatever is seen, heard, sensed or clung to, is esteemed as truth by
other folk. Midst those who are entrenched in their own views, being 'Such' I hold none as
true or false. This barb I beheld, well in advance [i.e., at
The foot of the Bodhi tree], whereon humans are hooked, impaled.
"I know, I see,'tis verily so"no such clinging for the Tathaagatas.
This scripture clarifies the Buddhist prescription "to see things
as they really are," since it implies that one should simply see without adding
anything. Recall the ancient Hermes epigram found on a Grecian urn: "Who shall say
more, will lie."(9) As to the 'barb' of the verse, the Paali is salla.m, equivalent
to the Vedic word 'salya, whichdown the centuries means an 'arrow', on which one is
impaled (if such be the case). I have cited this scripture in this essay because I do
believe that Vasubandhu's popularizing treatises have such a scriptural source in the
background.
About Cittamaatra. Past writings on this topic uniformly render the
term cittamaatra as 'mind only', and so do I also in my own former essays. Notice that
such renditions take the topic outside India by way of Asian translations and essays in
English and European languages. Inside India, where the term originated, the words citta
and maatra appeared as such with connotations of Sanskrit words; outside, there was the
connotation of the words 'mind' and 'only'.I propose to consider these words with their
connotation in the Sanskrit language.
In current lexical work I have learned various usages of the term
maatra.(10) The lexicons of India recognize a neuter form maatra.m and a feminine form
maatraa, so the adjectives can go with the neuter or the feminine Of the two definitions
for the neuter form 'all, the entirety' (kaartsnya), and 'restriction to the instance'
(avadhaara.na) the adjective 'only' could agree with 'restriction to the instance'. The
rendition 'only works for the other definition the entirety. For example, there is
the compound sthaanamaatra, in the meaning 'a place in general', thus any and all places
and excluding what is not a place. When cittamaatra is understood in this way, the citta
is unmixed with anything that is not citta. Accordingly, if we suppose in the compound
cittamaatra that maatra means 'only', then is only one of the two senses intended, or can
it be both?
It is well to point out that other adjectives are feasible from the
feminine maatraa. The definition 'any measure' (maana) yields the entry in Apte's
Sanskrit-English dictionary paromaatra ('vast') for the spatial measure and, in the
lexicons, tatkaalamaatra ('at once') for the temporal measure and also alpa ('a trifle')
as wellas ak.sibhaaga ('a mirror'). As adjectives applied to cittamaatra, we could say
'amounting to mind' both spatially and temporally. Or we could say 'just mind' and
'mirroring mind', and, for the latter, perhaps also 'being mirrored by mind'.
In a previously published essay, I presented Asa^nga's statement on
cittamaatra, which I translated in part.(11) It is clear that the Buddhist opponents did
not criticize on the grounds that Asa^nga denied the existence of the external world
(which, of course, he did not do). As the first attack, the opponent states: "it is
not valid that there is a mind-only in the sense of a 'continuous substantiality'
(dravyatas), because it contradicts scripture." The opponent is asked: "How does
it contradict scripture?" That person responds: "He (the Buddha) said, 'If the
citta consisted of lust defilement (upakle'sa) and consisted of hatred and delusion
defilement, it could not become liberated.'" Asa^nga replies: "But what is the
objection to that?" He seems to mean that we accept what the Buddha taught, and so if
the citta does not consist of these defilements (or contain them), it would be liberated;
hence your scriptural appeal cannot deny to mind-only a 'continuous substantiality'. The
opponent does not give up, and retorts: "Mind-only by itself is invalid, because if
there is not two together, when one does not resort to representation (vij~napti) of lust,
etc., one would be free (of those defilements) [which we know is not the case]."
The opponent is obviously a follower of the Buddhist Abhidharma, which
teaches that there is no citta without a caitta (caitasika- dharma) a mental'.(12) That we
cannot have a citta by itself is the second meaning I treated above, the 'totality' sense,
all citta, unmixed with anything else. But Asa^nga appears to espouse this 'totality'
sense. His response starts by saying "There is no fault in a prior
representation," and continues:
There is what was said by the Bhagavat, to wit, "concomitant
(sahaja) feeling (vedanaa), idea (sa.mjnaa), and thinking volition (cetanaa),"and
what was said (by Him), to wit, "These natures (dharma) are mingled, not unmingled,
sothese natures are not objects individually separated out; or when separated out (not
objects) for reference as distinct, or clear, or different." To demonstrate the
meaning of the mingling he used the simile of the light of a butter lamp.(13) Accordingly,
if they were not concomitant, it would also have been improper to say they are mingled.
Asa^nga has cited a scripture in Buddhist Sanskrit equivalent to the
Mahaavedalla- the individual factors, because they are mingled.
Presumably, it takes a yogin to separate the mental items. Then this
yogin can arrive at a pure citta. The Pata~njali Yogasuutra seems to have a similar idea
when it refers to 'cessation of the modifications of the citta' (cittavr.rtti-nirodha).
Now I shall deal with three subtopics: (1) the phrase cittamaatra.m yad
uta traidhaatukam, (2) the Yogaacaara theory of ekaagracitta, and (3) the theory that
Vasubandhu denies the external world.
The Phrase Cittamaatra.m yad uta traidhaatukam. There is a rather
famous passage in the Buddhist Da'sabhuumika-suutra, its Sixth Stage (bhuumi). This has
been cited as cittamaatra.m yad uta traidhaatukam, and the scripture's translation by
Megumu Honda, as revised by Professor Johannes Rahder, understands this to mean"This
triple world is mind-only."(14) Sylvain Levi, in a learned note at the beginning of
his French translation of Vasubandhu's Vi.m'satikaa (the Twenty Verses), presents several
versions of this formula, in each case showing the form traidhaatukam, and he appears to
recognize that the Da'sabhuumika-suutra is the source of such nonscriptural citations of
the entire formula.(15) This passage has seemed to support the claim that the Yogaacaara
denies the existence of the external world, as here, 'three worlds'--of desire, form, and
the formless worlds, according to the usual Buddhist dogmatics.
Now, one of the difficulties of the usual translation and consequent
interpretation is that this scripture, the Da'sabhuumika-suutra, is not really a
Yogaacaara scripture. Indeed it is a basic scripture of ahaayaana Buddhism and is not
devoted to the particular philosophical view of the Yogaacaara. The particular phrase was
inserted by that scripture within a discussion of Dependent Origination, which is
important to all Buddhist schools. Vasubandhu, in his great commentary on the
Da'sabhuumika-suutra, gives two explanations for this phrase, neither of which promotes
any particular theories of theYogaacaara school, even though the first explanation uses
the Yogaacaara theory of multiple vij~naanas.(16) This first explanation goes into the
Buddhist theory of waywardness (viparyaasa), and then announces that the 'mind-only'
passage was promulgated so that one may be liberated from the 'store consciousness'
(aalayavij~naana) and from other perceptions (vij~naana). Here, the sense of maatra.m
seems to be 'amounting to', that is,'amounting to mind', where the 'mind' (citta) here
stands for all the vij~naanas, counted as seven or eight. These are the perceptions
(vij~naana) based on the five outer-directed senses, the manovij~naana based on the mind
(manas) as an inner sense organ, and the 'store consciousness' (for 7), or number 7, the
'defiled mind' (kli.s.tamanas), plus the 'store consciousness' for 8. If someone of
Madhyamaka persuasion had been commenting, probably only the first six vij~naana would be
mentioned. Therefore, it is not a Particular Yogaacaara teaching here that is meant, but
simply that these various perceptions are what lead to waywardness (viparyaasa) and then
to rebirth according to the precepts of Dependent Origination. Vasubandhu was entitled to
interpret the term cittamaatra by the set of vij~naana because the Abhidharma gives the
terminological set citta, manas, vij~naana, which allows their mutual substitution in
certain contexts;(17) and Candrakiirti's autocommentary on his Madhyamakaavataara also
changes the cittamaatra of the famous formula about the'three worlds' to vij~naanamaatra
in his section attempting to refute the 'store consciousness' (aalayavij~naana).(18)
The second explanation has to do with the formula of Dependent
Origination, and here the'thought' is that of the Buddha, who realized the formula with
just one thought (ekacitta) and then taught it in a twelvefold way. Here, the meaning of
maatra.m is the temporal sense 'at once' or in temporal sequence when the twelve members
are taught one after another, thus taking time, eventually to have the theory that the
twelve amount to three lives.
And this information from Vasubandhu shows that the rendition of
traidhaatukam as 'three worlds' is incorrect.The Sanskrit term is a derivative noun from
'three worlds' (tridhaatu). The derivative nouns of Sanskrit have to be interpreted by
each such term. For example, Gautama is the derivative of Gotama; this is a family-type of
derivative such that Gautama is the descendent of Gotama. The derivative pauru.sa from
puru.sa (a human person or man) applies more to the present case, because as a masculine
noun pauru.sa can mean 'human action' (karman) and 'the weight that one man with both
hands can raise upwards' (uurdhvavist.rta-do.hpaa.nin.rmaana).(19) We can also interpret
traidhaatukam in two ways. Both ways take the derivative here to be the formula of
twelvefold Dependent Origination, that is, that it is derived from, or faithful to, the
three worlds, so realized in one moment's thought by the Buddha and then taught in twelve
terms. This one-moment's thought is a variety of cittamaatra. The other interpretation of
the twelvefold formula is that it is the way of rebirth through waywardness due to the set
of Vij~naana, and this is a different interpretation of cittamaatra. But rebirth requires
that is, is related tothethree worlds. Neither of Vasubandhu's explanations in this
commentary justifies the interpretation that the passage, so misrendered to wit,
"This triple world is mind-only" has anything to do with denying the existence
of the external world.
The natural question, then, is how should that Sanskrit phrase be
rendered? I would offer: the derivative of the three worlds is only mind. That is to say,
whatever may be the 'three worlds' in a minimal sense whatever else is attributed to them,
an elaboration of them, a product of them has been added by the mind. In one case it was
added by the mind of the Buddha the twelvefold formula of Dependent Origination. In the
other case it was added by the mind of other sentient beings. Hence, such an observation
agrees with the scripturetranslated above, the Kaa.lakaaraama Sutta, which gave the
message that to see things as they really are, one must not add anything. Apparently the
six senses (when normal) see things as they really are, and it is the perceptions
(vij~naana) based thereon that do the adding. But this is the interpretation of
cittamaatra when it is tantamount to the set of vij~naana. This shows that it was proper
for me to cite that scripture as a background of Vasubandhu's position.
Besides, the large chapter 3 of Vasubandhu's Abhidharmako'sa and his
own commentary is devoted to the worlds, which, when in two sets, are the world of
sentience (sattva-loka) and the support world (bhaajana-loka).(20) He was therefore very
familiar with the respective attributions of these two kinds of worlds. He would
undoubtedly know of the scripture in the Diigha-nikaaya, III, called Agga~n~na-sutta
(though in the Buddhist Sanskrit AAgama version) a scripture on the Buddhist theory of
genesis. One may read the account in the translation of the Paali-version that, after a
long period, this world passes away. This is the Indian theory of cycles, with the passing
away and emergence of the 'support world'. The scripture mentions that with the passing
away the sentient beings had retreated to a 'higher' realm that of Form (ruupa-dhaatu) and
while the world was plunged in watery darkness, they were 'made of mind, fed on
joy, and were self-luminous. The earth reappeared like a scum on the
cooling water and became endowed with color, odor, and taste. The sentient beings tasted
this and found it very sweet. As they ate more and more, they gradually lost their
self-luminance, while the moon and sun became manifest. The beings had evidently fallen
into the realm of desire.(21) In such an account we see the prior disappearance and
reappearance of the support world, and that the sentient world follows suit. Accordingly,
the way of translating that phrase about cittamaatra and the traidhaatuka that I have had
to discard, namely that the three worlds are dependent upon citta, would have been in
direct violation of the Genesis story. I don't believe that Vasubandhu would have taken a
position in his brief popularizing works in direct opposition to the Buddhist scriptures.
The Yogaacaara Theory of Ekaagracitta. It was pointed out above that
the Buddha was credited with realizing the entire formula of Dependent Origination with
"one-moment's thought." In that place, the term was ekacitta. The theory of
Buddhist meditation sets forth a goal called samaadhi, which is defined as ekaagracitta.
This term has frequently been rendered "one-pointed thought (or mind)." Then
what is meant by the Sanskrit word agra? Since this is an important term in the Sanskrit
language, the Indian lexicographers have had to make it a defined word. Over four of their
lexicons include for it the definition aalambana.(22) Literally, this means a 'support'.
Many years ago I learned that this is the basic term in Buddhism for the 'reflected image'
in the mind,(23) which is what one should meditate upon, given that it is an appropriate
object for such meditative purposes. It follows that such a definition permits a
translation for the entire compound ekaagracitta, namely "mind on a single meditative
topic." Also, see Vasubandhu's Abhidharmako'sa, chapter 1, for a similar distinction
between the outer sense object (vi.saya) and the mental reflection (aalambana).(24)
Besides, three of these four lexicons also defined the expression
ekaagra, namely as "a single continuity" (ekataana) and as "being without
discord" (anaakula). So the expression ekaagracitta can be further explained for the
practice of a yogin, to wit, "the mind or consciousness as a single continuity and as
without discord."(25) The two definitions go together, because the continuity would
be broken if the mind were subjected to discord. And in such a case there would not be a
"single meditative object." This is an implicationof the definition I found,
namely ekataana, because this contrasts with a well-known Buddhist term, sa.mtaana, which
is usually understood as a "stream of consciousness, " but which the foregoing
information suggests should be better rendered as a"mingled stream of
consciousness." I should call attention to the fact that the prefix sam- in Sanskrit
is cognate with an Indo-European prefix that is present in English as con- in the sense of
"together," that is, that in the ordinary case of a sa.mtaana, the continuity
(taana) is composite. Therefore, when a modern Tibetan author, Lozang Tsewang, in a
published seminar paper, writes, "Lord Buddha says in the suutras: 'The consciousness
of a sentient being is of a single stream'"(26) (but does not identify the suutra so
saying), the cited passage might mean what I called attention to above, that although the
mental factors are mingled, a yoginif successful may separate out the citta and find it
consisting of a single stream. But it is important to notice that the yogin does this with
his own mind, and because he is engrossed in asamaadhi. He does not do this separating out
in the minds of other sentient beings, who cannot verifythat the consciousness is of a
single stream, forthe reasons that the mental factors are mingled and that they have not
learned how to go into the appropriate samaadhi. This Tibetan author attempted to apply
that cited passage in a philosophical treatment of the Yogaacaara position. But it is not
valid to argue that something is the case with all minds (and their presumed objects) when
it was only the case of a certain yogin and his personal attainment.
The Theory that Vasubandhu Denies the External World. Certainly some
readers decided that Vasubandhu's twenty-verse treatise (the Vi.m'saatikaa) involves a
denial of the external world. And such persons are entitled to say: suppose we grant your
previous argument about cittamaatra and the traidhaatuka. Even so there are verses in
that Vasubandhu treatise that appear to deny the external world. Before
going into those particular verses, it is well to notice the situation in his
Abhidharmako'sa. Abhidharma Buddhism recognizes six senses and their objects, from the
sense of eye with its object of formations (in shape or color) to the sense of mind
(manas) with its object of natures (dharma). But this does not mean that one necessarily
perceives such sense objects. So Buddhism taught that there is a 'perception' (vij~naana)
based on the eye, and so with the other senses as bases (aayatana). Because the senses had
the power to apprehend those various objects, they were given the Sanskrit name indriya, a
word which means 'a power'. It follows immediately that 'perception' ispowerless; that is,
it is unable to contact the object directly, but must depend on whatever the sense organ
comes up with.
Bareau presents the manner in which Vasubandhu treated this matter in
his Abhidharmako'sa:(27) ruupa.m pa~ncendriyaa.ny arthaa.h pa~ncaavij~naptir eva ca (1, 9)
("Formation is five sense organs, five objects, and non-representation");
cak.su.h pa'syati ruupaa.ni sabhaaga.m na tadaa'srita.m vij~naana.m d.r'syate ruupa.m na
kilaantarita.m yata.h (I, 42) (Bareau's translation: "When it is in condition to
work, the eye sees formations; the consciousness which is leaning on it does not (see
formations), because formation, then being concealed, is not seen"). If we grant that
perception fails to reach the object that was apprehended by a sense organ, we begin to
notice how perception, perhaps automatically, adds to the sensory evidence, as was
discussed above. And this may help to explain why the same art object is viewed
differently by different persons presumably it was about the same as a sense object, but
the subjective perceptions evaluate it quite divergently.
Now to the twenty-verse treatise. The translation from the Chinese by
Hamilton(28) was reprinted in A Source Book by Radhakrishnan and Moore.(29) We learn there
that these twenty verses are on vij~naptimaatrataa, there rendered 'Representation-Only'.
It is somewhat embarrassing to me to point out what the editorshave added in their
footnote on page 328, because I have always had great admiration for both Radhakrishnan
and Moore. They say: "A better translation of vij~naptimaatrataa would be
'ideation-only, ' since 'representation' suggests rather than denies external
reality." Well, no fair mistranslating a Sanskrit term just to make one's theory come
out right! That remark was made because of thinking that Vasubandhu's treatise denies
external reality.
Sylvain Levi's edition (30) of the Sanskrit for the twenty verses
numbers them as twenty-two. His verse 1 can be taken as introductory, and his verse 22 as
concluding. The translation from the Chinese, as presented by Hamilton, starts with
Sanskrit number 2 as the first verse. This is Levi's introductory verse with my
translation:
- vij~naptimaatram evaitad asadarthaavabhaasanaat/
- yathaa taimirikasyaasatke'sacandraadidar'sana.m//
This just amounts to representation, as the sight of unreal hair, moon,
etc. of one with an eye caul because being the (subsequent) manifestation of an unreal
artha (external thing).
This introductory statement does not deny an external object. Instead
there is a mental representation that amounts to tinsel, 'fool's gold',
a false wealth. Vasubandhu appears to mean that the mind imagines an
external artha in front, but the mind has only a report or representation of what the
sense organ had sensed.
This is Levi's verse, and what for both the Chinese and the Tibetan is
verse 1, with my rendition (Levi had to reconstruct the Sanskrit):
- yadi vij~naptir anarthaa niyamo de'sakaalayoh/
- sa.mtaanasyaaniyama's ca yuktaa k.rtyakriyaa na ca //
If representation lacks an external object (artha), there is no
certainty (aniyama) of space and time; there is no certainty of the composite stream (of
consciousness) and agency is not valid.
We notice again that Vasubandhu does not here deny an external object,
because the sentence makes a supposition, "If...." The verses go on to make a
distinction between the beings of different destinies, gods, humans, hungry ghosts, and so
forth, in how they view externals. Thus the gods see the river sparkling with gems, humans
see it as good to drink, and the hungry ghosts (preta) find the river full of unclean
things rendering it unfit to drink. We notice this difference in terms of destiny classes
that it involves the use of external things. Again, it is not a denial of external
objects, but a claim that different destinies have a different addition (philosophically
false) to what was sensed. Then there is what is numbered verse 16 in Hamilton's
translation, where he renders the first part as follows: "As has been said, the
apparent object is a presentation. It is from that memory arises" (the Sanskrit for
this: ukta.m yathaa
tadaabhaasaavij~napti.h; smara.na.m tata.h). Hamilton translates the
commentary on this:(31) "As we have said earlier, although there is no external
object, a sense representation, visual, etc., appears as an outer object. From this comes
the later state with its memory associate, the discriminated mental representation,
appearing as a seeming former object. Then we speak of this as a memory of what has been
already experienced." Notice that Hamilton translated the first sentence of this
commentary as though there is denial of the copula ("although there is no external
object"). But when we consult the Sanskrit that Levi edited, we find the sentence
worded differently: "Even in the absence of an external object" (vinaapy
arthena). It is necessary to translate this way to make sense of the comment that Hamilton
translates from Chinese:(32) "That is, he defends his position by saying that there
must have been this object immediately received in the past by the five organs of sense,
eye, etc. [so that] in the present the intellective consciousness is able to hold it in
memory."
We have probably all had such an experience, when concentrating on some
problem or passage, if someone comes to the door and says, "Dinner is ready"
and, not immediately hearing a response of the type "O.K. I'm coming, "
continues, "I said: 'Dinner is ready'! "whereupon the concentrating person
responds, "I heard you the first time" not exactly as this person now says it,
because if we mean by hearing the actual sounds as heard at the time the sounds are made,
this is true just for the reception by a sense organ (of hearing), and not true for
auditory perception. According to Vasubandhu, as the Chinese commentary here understood
him, the person remembered the words "Dinner is ready." Thus, "even in the
absence of an external object, "that is, even though that sound is no longer
sounding, a person may hear it as a memory image. Due to the actual experiences of yogins,
this situation was taken for granted. There is a celebrated case associated with what in
Buddhist history is called the Second Council, to determine if certain erring monks should
be ousted from the Sa.mgha: all the senior monks were called to assemble for the hearings,
but one of these monks was in the deep concentration called nirodha-samaapatti. According
to the story, upon hisemerging from the samaadhi a divinity gave him the message,
whereupon he sped to the meeting.(33) It should be admitted that this yogin remembered the
message, while the instigating sound was no longer sounding.
Thus, when we examine the text more carefully, we find that Vasubandhu
does not deny the existence of external objects in this and in the previously cited
materials, even though the translator, just by his manner of translating, made it appear
so. Besides, two authors of recent books translating a number of the Vasubandhu treatises
agree that Vasubandhu does not deny an external object (Kochumuttom(34) and Anacker(35)).
As to Murti's chapter, previously alluded to, a few words will suffice.
A reader of that chapter, supposedly on the 'absolutism' of Vedaanta,
Maadhyamika, and vij~naanavaada, will readily find out that the
Yogaacaara position (called here 'Vij~naanavaada') is set forth, not from Yogaacaara
books, but from their rival Vedaanta and Maadhyamika
books. Having decided that the opponents must be right, when he then
cites a Yogaacaara treatise it must be made to agree with Murti's supposition. So,
referring to the Madhyaantavibhaaga, he says, "The
constructed subject-object world is unreal; but this does not make the
abhuutaparikalpa unreal; for, it is the substratum for the unreal subject-object duality.
It is, however, non-conceptual."(36) So
abhuutaparikalpa, which means "the imagination of what did not
(really) happen," is 'non-conceptual'! I conclude that Murti in this chapter does not
advance the understanding of Yogaacaara Buddhism.
About Alayavij~naana. When we turn to the Yogaacaara theories that
devolve about the term aalayavij~naana, we notice that what must have been a hotly
contested point even in the time of the Buddhist master Asa^nga is still in present times
disputed. I already mentioned that there is a two-volume work on the topic by
Schmithausen. Here, under a heading "Introduction and Original Meaning of
AAlayavij~naana," he points to a passage in the Samaahitabhuumi portion of the
Yogaacaarabhuumi about a person in the deep concentration called nirodha-samaapatti, and
that it is a continuance of the aalayavij~naana with its seeds, which shows that even
though various other mental functions have ceased, vij~naana itself has not ceased, and
these seeds will bring forth the evolving types of vij~naana when the person emerges from
the samaadhi.(37) Schmithausen calls this the "Initial Passage" here and a
number of times later on in his work. He goes on to claim (38) that the passage, although
not stating this explicitly, implies that the continued presence of the aalayavij~naana
has kept alive that yogin who is in nirodha-samaapatti. And if that is so, then the
aalayavij~naana must also be associated with the moment of conception in the womb, (39)
and so this is the vij~naana on which Name-and-Formation (naama-ruupa) arises in
dependence in the usual sequence of the Buddhist Dependent Origination. Accordingly, he
insists that the pratisa.mdhi (or 'linking', the 'rebirth') kind of vij~naana is that
initial aalayavij~naana that descends into the male-female element union in the womb.(40)
In the course of his investigation he was led to disagree with various
Japanese scholars who understood these matters differently from him. I shall have to
evaluate whether his conclusions are consistent with the positions of Asa^nga, the founder
of the Yogaacaara, or of Vasubandhu, the great popularizer thereof. It happens that
Asa^nga himself obviously responding to a number of challenges and condemnations of this
aalayavij~naana position gave his answers in the opening section of his exegetical section
called Vini'scayasa.mgraha.nii, which I employ in the Tibetan version in the Tanjur. There
we learn that the 'store consciousness' is the abode of seeds (aalayavij~naana.m
biijaa'sraya.h) .(41)Asa^nga claims that this is a secret teaching of the Bhagavat, citing
a well-known verse from the Sa.mdhinirmocana-suutra about the aadaanavij~naana (the
consciousness that 'takes' [seeds]).(42) But the reader of this section cannot avoid the
conclusion that Asa^nga is convinced that of the many references to vij~naana in the old
Buddhist Sanskrit canon (the four AAgamas) that he employed, they cannot all be explained
as the standard six perceptions based on the six sense organs, but that there are various
contexts of this Sanskrit expression which justify it to be understood differently.
Now, as Asa^nga continues in his defense of this type of vij~naana, he
sets forth three reasons that surprisingly were not referred to by Schmithausen. I shall
cite the Tibetan along with my translation below each passage, and then follow with a
discussion insofar as it is possible.
/ ci'i phyir kun gzhi rnam par 'ses pa med na lus kyi tshor ba mi rung
zhe na / 'di ltar tshul bzhin nas tshul bzhin ma yin pa sems par byed pa dang / rjes su
rtog par byed pa'am / sems mnyam par bzhag pa'am / sems mnyam par ma bzhag pagcig cig lus
la tshor ba rnam pa du ma rnam pa
mang po sna tshogs gang dag 'byung ba'i rigs na snang ste / de'i phyir
yang kun gzhi rnam par 'ses pa yod do /(43)
1. Why in the absence of aalayavij~naana is the body's feeling not
feasible? It is this way: when positing that the mind attends in the right
manner and then imagines in the wrong manner; or that the mind is
equipoised, then is not equipoised, there appear principles that bring
forth a multitude of aspects of varied kinds of feelings in a certain
body. Therefore, there is the 'store-consciousness'.
/ ci'i phyir kun gzhi rnam par 'ses pa med na sems med pa'i snyoms par
'jug pa mi srid ce na / 'di ltar 'du 'ses med pa la snyoms par zhugs
pa'am/ 'gog pa la snyoms par zhugs pa'i rnam par'ses pa lus dang bral
ba kho nar 'gyur zhing ma bral bar mi 'gyur bas / de'i phyir 'si ba kho nar 'gyur ba zhig
na bcom ldan 'das kyi de skad du / de'i rnam par 'ses pa ni lus dang bral ba ma yin no
zhes gsungs pa'i phyir ro /(44)
2. Why in the absence of aalayavij~naana would there be no possibility
of equipoise without thought (acittika-samaapatti)? It is this way: the vij~naana that is
in non-ideational equipoise (asa.mj~nika-samaapatti) or is in cessation equipoise
(nirodha-samaapatti) only occurs when it is absent from the body, and would not occur
[that way] when not absent (from the body). For that reason, it was only for the case of
death that the Bhagavat declared, "his vij~naana is not absent from the body."
/ ci'i phyir kun gzhi rnam par 'ses pa med na 'chi 'pho mi rung zhe na
/ 'di ltar 'pho ba'i tshe'i rnam par 'ses pas lus ro stod dam / ro smad du drod yal bar
byed cing spong la yid kyi rnam par 'ses pa ni nam yang mi 'byung ba ma yin bas / de'i
phyir lus len par byed pa'i kun gzhi rnam par 'ses pa kho na dang bral bas lus kyi drod
yal ba dang / lus la tshor ba med par snang bar zad kyi / yid kyi rnam par 'ses pa dang
bral bas ni ma yin te / de'i phyir yang mi rung ngo/(45)
3. Why in the absence of aalayavij~naana is there no feasibility of
transmigration? It is this way: the vij~naana at the time of [dyingand] transmigrating
leaves when the warmth of the upper and lower parts of the body fades away, and the
manovij~naana certainly does not occur and is not [at that time]. On that account, only in
the absence of the aalayavij~naana which takes a body does feeling (vedanaa) get lost in
the body, but this does not happen through the absence of manovij~naana. So there is no
feasibility (in the absence of aalayavij~naana).
One of the first conclusions about these three passages is that
Schmithausen was wrong in concluding that aalayavij~naana was necessary so that a
meditator who is in the trance state nirodha-samaapatti would not die there. Certainly, if
Asa^nga had thought so, this would be the place for him to have said so. It is a case when
vij~naana departs from the body, but the person does not die(on that account). But when a
person does die, vij~naana does depart from the body. However, the three passages
certainly require further explanations. A certain amount of explication should come
through considering certain Schmithausen claims as were eluded to above.
As to his view that the aalayavij~naana is the kind of vij~naana that
descends into the male-female element union in the womb, supposedly bringing life thereto,
there is Asa^nga's own explanation in the early part of the Yogaacaarabhuumi:
[tatra] sarvabiijaka.m vipaakasa.mg.rhiitam aa'srayopaa adaanaad
aalayavij~naana.msammuurcchati /(46)
There, the 'store-consciousness' all-seeded and restrained by
maturation, after taking a body, faints (or falls unconscious, or becomes inactive).
And:
yatra ca kalalade'se tad vij~naana.m sammuurcchita.m so 'sya bhavati
tasmin samayeh.rdayade'sa.h /(47)
Where that vij~naana faints in a place of the kalala (initial form of
the embryo), it [that place] becomes for it [the embryo] at that time the place of the
heart. Notice that in this account, the initial form of the embryo after conception is
already there when the 'store consciousness' enters. The term kalala is used in Indian
medicine for the initial embryo. So it is a case like the Genesis account already
mentioned where the support world precedes the subjective element. Thus while Schmithausen
was right about the role of aalayavij~naana to represent in some way the vij~naana that is
the third member of Dependent Origination, and so to fall into the womb (in the human
case), it is clear that Asa^nga does not, and would not, ascribe to vij~naana the role of
conferring life as Schmithausen claimed. These remarks help to explain somewhat the third
of Asa^nga's defenses of the aalayavij~naana.
Then Schmithausen claimed, and repeated his claim, that this
aalayavij~naana that falls into the womb is the pratisa.mdhi (rebirth) type of vij~naana.
Apparently because some pandits were espousing such a theory at the time of Vasubandhu, he
countered it in no uncertain terms in his Dependent Origination commentary: "it is
not right that the pratisa.mdhivij~naana is by way of sa.mskaara [the second member of
Dependent Origination]. It is true that vij~naana arises [as the third member]; the
Name-and-formation (naama-ruupa) [as the fourth member] arising on that basis is the time
of pratisa.mdhi this is the faultless position."(48) Gu.namati claims that
Vasubandhu's Abhidharmako'sa identifies the pratisa.mdhi ('linkage' reincarnation) with
the skandha kind of vij~naana.(49) He presumably means chapter 3, the introductory
paragraph to k. 14, where the first line in the Sanskrit text has the expression
"five upaadaana-skandha," and in the next line it says "The moment of
pratisa.mdhi is the birth in the destinies (gati) " (upapattibhavo gati.su
pratisa.mdhik.sa.na.h).(50)
Buddhaghosa helps to make sense of the foregoing when, in his famous
work Visuddhimagga, he sets forth under the topic of the fourth member of Dependent
Origination that the naaman (of naama-ruupa), when initially developing in the womb,
consists of three aggregates. That is, he defines it, vedanaadayo tayo khandhaa, "the
three personal aggregates, feelings, etc.,"(51) thus leaving out vi~n~naana (the
Paali way of writing vij~naana), while the standard Abhidharma listing of the naaman part
presents the four members, including vij~naana. This forces the well-known canonical
passage holding that naama-ruupa arises in dependence on vij~naana and that vij~naana
arises in dependence on naama-ruupa to mean that vij~naana is added to the foundation of
reifying views
(satkaayad.r.s.tyadhi.s.thaana), and foundation of 'I am' pride
(asmimaanaadhi.s.thaana) and any others belonging to the same set.(52) Besides, Asa^nga
gives a list of various outcomes of these seeds: family (kula), strength (bala), bodily
appearance(ruupa), length of life (aayus), enjoyments (bhoga), and so on; and of these
effects, principally good ('subha) and bad (a'subha) karma is the cause.(53)
Later, Asa^nga told how this 'store consciousness' gets its seeds:
evam avyaak.rtaa dharmaa ku'salaaku'salaavyaak.rtaan dharmaan aavahanti
/ tadyathaa ku'salaaku'salaavyaak.rtabiijakam
aalayavij~naanam aavahanti /(54)
Thus,the indeterminate natures (avyaak.rtadharma) bring the virtuous,
unvirtuous, and indeterminate natures, as follows: they bring (them) to the 'store
consciousness', which is seeded with the virtuous, unvirtuous, and indeterminate.
Previously it was mentioned that the Yogaacaara frequently presents a
list of eight vij~naana, of which number 7 is the 'defiled manas' and number 8 is the
aalayavij~naana. Now, in Buddhist commentarial exegesis of the scriptures, there was a
problem with the vij~naana that is third in Dependent Origination, and was said to have
a'vision' of the birthplace and so to be attracted thereto. Now, even in the Yogaacaara,
it would hardly be feasible to identify this third member with the aalayavij~naana, since
a store of seeds could hardly be called visionary, except for the envisioning of effects,
as an acorn might be said (poetically or metaphorically) to foresee the oak tree. But
however we might credit the acorn with such an ability, we should all admit that the acorn
cannot imagine where it will grow. Vasubandhu was well aware of the difficulty, so in his
Mahaayaasa.mgraha commentary he said: Besides, when the manovij~naana that is defiled
witnesses the birthplace, the intermediate state [between death and rebirth] comes to an
end. That it "faints" means that the manovij~naana comes together with the male
and female generative elements, [and] experiences a single [moment of] bliss, whereupon
the manovij~naana faints [i.e., becomes unconscious or inactive], and on the basis
thereof, a different sort of manovij~naana enters."(55)
Since Asa^nga had already denied that the manovij~naana (i.e., the one
based on the manas as the sixth sense) is operative at the time of death, Vasubandhu must
mean the seventh vij~naana, what in later Yogaacaara was referred to as the 'defiled mind'
(kli.s.ta-manas). Later, Vasubandhu comments: "Therefore, the manovij~naana that
faints is not [i.e., is no longer] a manovij~naana, but is a vipaaka-vij~naana [i.e., a
resultative kind]; and that is 'all-seeded'."(56) He therefore admits that it was the
'defiled mind' that falls into the womb and, once there, is called aalayavij~naana. This
separate category of a 'defiled mind' seems to have been adopted for the death vision, for
the visions during the intermediate state (antaraabhava), for the birth vision, and
perhaps also (just my own speculation) for hypnogogic states during a lifetime.
Now, as this 'store consciousness' is credited with having a store of
'all' dharmas, we should recall that in Buddhist Abhidharma it is the manovij~naana that
has those dharmas supposedlyas object, while it is the sixth sense manas that has those
dharmas directly as object. In the theory of Dependent Origination alluded to above, for a
vij~naana that arises in dependence on Name-and-Formation, Gu.namati explains that the
manovij~naana is the main one: "Given the set of six vij~naana, only manovij~naana is
the fastening (Tib. sbrel ba) of pratisa.mdhi (the reincarnation)."(57)
This means that the fourth member Name-and-Formation is necessary for
the Abhidharma manovij~naana to operate; so the remaining vij~naanas, based on the five
outer-directed senses, must require the fifth member, the Six Sensory Bases
(.sa.daayatana), to operate.
All the foregoing should clarify that the chief demand to have the
concept of aalayavij~naana was for Asa^nga's third reason the theory of rebirth.
Schmithausen's theory that the initial place is the context of a
special yoga state that is, nirodha-samaapatti is hardly tenable. The discussion at some
length in the early part of the Yogaacaarabhuumi shows that it was the Buddhist arguments
over whether some persons had or did not have the potentiality of Nirvaa.na,(58) and the
attempt to justify events of the present day as the effect of previous lives, that
demanded a carrier of a seed-nature. This must be why Asa^nga allows for the operation of
aalayavij~naana when the 'evolving perceptions' are in abeyance.(59)
But then there are the first and second reasons that Asa^nga mentioned.
These are quite difficult because yoga states are implicated. When Asa^nga mentioned, as
cited above, that vij~naana entered the embryo at the place where the heart would form,
this makes it clear that when he said in the second reason that in the case of those two
kinds of samaapatti the vij~naana is absent from the body, it means that vij~naana had
left its 'heart' location, and was somewhere else for the time being (in the head?). This
suggests that the yogin is in a sort of cataleptic state. And this seems to be why, in the
first reason, Asa^nga had credited the 'store consciousness' with enabling the feelings of
the body. Thus, in certain trance states there is a local or more general loss of feeling,
and Asa^nga claims that to understand what is going on in these specialized states, one
must posit a 'store consciousness'. This appears to be enough for these three reasons, as
far as this essay is concerned.
It would also take too much space to go into the matter of the
transmutation of the 'store consciousness' (aalayavij~naana-pariv.rtti), and the matter of
which advanced persons a Buddha, an arhat, advanced bodhisattvas, and so on have
transmuted this 'store consciousness' and so do not possess it.(60) But this teaching
shows that the aalayavij~naana theory does not require it for the yoga experience of
ekaagracitta, as it was discussed above, which implies a special condition of the evolving
perceptions, especially manovij~naana (the perception based on the mental sense of mind,
manas).
About Three Lak.sa.nas. There is considerable treatment already in
Western sources on the three lak.sa.nas of Yogaacaara theory that are also called the
three svabhaava. Nagao has written a spirited essay on the topic, "The Buddhist World
View as Elucidated in the Three-Nature Theory and its Similes."(61) As Nagao
describes the three, they are the imagined nature (parikalpita-svabhaava), the other
dependent nature (paratantra-svabhaava), and the consummated nature
(parini.spanna-svabhaava). And he explains: "The 'imagined' nature, therefore, is
characterized by 'unreality' and 'total nonexistence'." "In contrast to this,
parini.spanna or 'consummated' means perfect, real, and existent and connotes
'reality, 'truth,' 'real existence', or 'the absolute'." "Between them is
the third nature, called paratantra, the 'other dependent'. It exists, but only by
depending on some other entity."(62)
Nagao cites an important observation from Vasubandhu's Tri.m'sikaa, k.
21c-d: "When the other-dependen nature obtains a state absolutely free of the
imagined nature, it is then the consummated nature."(63)
It is the conclusion of the present writer that this system of three
natures is very close to what is found in the writings of the earlier and famous
Naagaarjuna, with the difference that the Yogaacaara thought it was
improving in describing what is going on. I allude to two verses in the latter's
Acintyastava, 44-45:(64)
- hetupratyayasambhuutaa paratantraa ca sa.mv.rti.h / paratantra iti prokta.h paramaarthas
tv ak.rtrima.h //44 svabhaava.h prak.rtis tattva.m dravya.m vastu sad ity api / naasti vai
kalpito bhaavo
- paratantras tu vidyate //45
Convention, with dependence on other(s) (paratantra), arises from a
cause an from conditions. This dependence on other(s) has been announced (byThee). The
Absolute is not fabricated. (44) It (the Absolute) is termed self-existence (svabhaava),
primary nature (prak.rti), reality (tattva), substance (dravya), abiding essence (vastu),
the really existent (sat). An entity (bhaava) when imagined does not exist, but (exists)
when its dependence on other(s) is found. (45)
Notice the complete agreement with the Yogaacaara that an entity when
imagined does not exist, but does exist with its dependence on another; and the same word
for dependence on another (paratantra) is used. Naagaarjuna, like the Yogaacaarin
espousers of the three svabhaava theory, has an absolute, defined by six terms. The only
seeming difference is when Vasubandhu holds that this absolut nature is the other
dependent nature when the latter is free of the imagined nature. This amounts to accepting
for Dependent Origination (pratiityasamutpaada) that there is both a conventional and an
absolute explanation. Even if Naagaarjuna accepts this, it would probably be difficult to
draw it from his works. This brief account of the three natures should suffice.
Clarification of the Position
Here I present three clarifications: (a) in terms of subject and
object, (b) in terms of Buddhist logic, and (c) in terms of Western discourse.
Clarification in Terms of Subject and Object.
Previously I discussed the position in Vasubandhu's treatise of twenty
verses and rejected the claim that he denied external existence. But more needs to be said
about this. Vasubandhu in this brief work of his used the term artha for the presumed
external object. Thereby he could only implicate the five outer-directed sense bases that
have these arthas as
objects. The word artha in its general Indian usage stands for property
and goods, and of course these stay behind when a person passes to the other world.
This usage of the term seems to be involved in its etymology.(65) The
sixth sense, manas, has the set of dharmas as object; and by the indian theory of
transmigration, some of these may well be held to transmigrate.
Let us now consider the treatment in Matilal's book Perception. In an
"Analysis of Perceptual Illusion" he has a subsection on two Buddhist
analyses of illusion, admitting that he follows Vaacaspati Mi'sra for
these materials; and this is quite proper, because he aims just not to
misrepresent the Hindu author. Matilal summarizes the Yogaacaara
position in seemingly well-stated sentences, which I shall number: (1) "The
object-form is an integral part of the awareness itself, each awareness being different
from another by virtue of this unique object-form which appears in it." (2) "The
object form does not come from outside."(3) "in fact when the object-form is
projected outside or externalized, we are said to have an awareness of the external
object."(66) In all three statements, Matilal attributes to theYogaacaara that there
is an 'object-form' in the mind. But when we refer to what Vasubandhu said (in his
Vi.m'saatikaa), we find him explaining the 'representation-only' not as an artha, the
external object, but as an 'unreal object form' (asadartha)-a poor copy of the external
object. Such a term affirms, rather than denies, what is connoted by the term artha, when
it is employed by itself. Vasubandhu apparently used the term artha instead of the
standard Buddhist vi.saya to fend off misattributions of the position he followed. Still,
he was misunderstood, and these misunderstandings were copied over and over.
Then there is the essay in Philosophy East and West by Prasad, who,
like Matilal, is a good writer on these topics.(67) He cites Vasubandhu's treatise on the
three natures, the Trisvabhaavanirde'sa, as follows:
What is the conception of that which is nonexistent? [The answer is]
'mind' [mental projection] / For by it, the nonexistents are imagined; and inasmuch as the
mind imagines objects, they do not exist at all.
What is that which is presented in cognition? The non-existent which is
projected [or imagined]. How is that presented in cognition? In the form of a twofold
appearance [of the apprehender and the apprehended] / What is it in cognition that does
not exist? That by which the twofold appearance is affected. Using the Sanskrit for the
verses as is found in Kochumuttom,(68) I accept Prasad's translation as on the whole
correct. In the case of the second of his cited verses, his rendition may possibly mislead
the reader, as suggesting that a nonexistent external has appeared in the mind. I believe
that here we should adhere more literally to the Sanskrit: tatra ki.m khyaati asatkalpa.h
katham khyaati dvayaatmanaa ("What appears there? The imagination of an unreal. How
does it appear? As the subject-object duality"). This subject-object duality is found
discussed in Buddhist literature generally by the terms graahaka (the apprehender) and
graahya (the apprehended). The avoidance of the two is the topic of the scripture
presented above, the Kaa.lakaaraama Sutta. Thus, when Vasubandhu writes such verses, he
evidently believes that they are consistent with the Buddha's teachings.
Clarification in Terms of Buddhist Logic. Stcherbatsky and others
claimed that there is a pronounced influence of Yogaacaara philosophy on Buddhist logic of
the Dignaaga-Dharmakiirti lineage.(69) If one is to credit the Yogaacaara with such
influence, one should state the influence rather specifically. I have previously published
three essays on this matter, "Yogaacaara and the Buddhist Logicians, "(70)
"A Reconsideration of Dharmakiirti's 'Deviation' from Dignaaga on
Pratyak.saabhaasa,"(71) and "Dharmakiirti and theYogaacaara Theory of
Biija."(72) In the first of these essays I translated Dignaaga's brief treatise, the
Alambanapariik.saa, which deals with the theory of 'atoms', which Vasubandhu also dealt
with in his twenty-verse treatise. I also cited the commentator Dharmottara's passage
explaining the so-called atoms as constituting color (var.na), while the shape
(sa.msthaana) was added, presumably in Representation-Only. The article "A
Reconsideration..." defended Dharmakiirti's position that there are four kinds of
falsification of perception (pratyak.saabhaasa) and that this was also Dignaaga's
position. The one on Dharmakiirti and biija showed that Dharmakiirti was amenable to this
'seed' way of talking.
Among the many authors who claim this Yogaacaara influence is C. L.
Tripathi, who wrote a book titled The Problems of Knowledge in Yogaacaara Buddhism that
included a treatment of Buddhist logic. He is
among the many who think that Yogaacaara Buddhism denies external
existence, saying: "Vasubandhu...categorically denies the existence of the external
world."(73) Yet this same author has a chapter "Object of Perception"
presenting the position of Buddhist logic that the object called svalak.sa.na is the only
real.(74) He calls it a 'particular', using the Western terminology of 'universal' and
'particular'. This author seems not to realize that if the Yogaacaara does indeed deny
external objects, it opposes Buddhist logic and so why treat Buddhist logic in a book with
such a title? Now I shall continue the discussion with the 'falsification of perception',
because this apparently agrees with the Yogaacaara 'representation only'. Vasubandhu's
commentary on the Mahaayaasa.mgraha, its chapter 2, speaks of 'representations'
(vij~napti) belonging to the body, the body-possessor, and the eater. Here 'body' means
the five realms (dhaatu) of (sense organs), eye, and so forth. 'Body-possessor' is the
'defiled mind'.
The 'eater' (or enjoyer) is the realm of mind (manodhaatu), that is,
mind (manas), the sixth sense.(75) Another relevant passage is in
Vasubandhu's Karmasiddhiprakara.na (I translate from the Tibetan):
"There are two kinds of citta:
- what collects its seeds (aalayavij~naana);
- (2-a) what has it (i.e., the aalayavij~naana) as a mental support (aalambana), namely
the 'defiled mind' (kli.s.tamanas);
(2-b) what has images (aakaara) of it (i.e., the aalayavij~naana),
namely the manovij~naana;
[and] (2-c) what have differing distinctions, namely the five
outer-directed perceptions (vij~naana)."(76) So the 'defiled mind' knows the
(subconscious) aalayavij~naana seeds, while the manovij~naana distinguishes the
(conscious) images that the seeds have sprouted into. Then we notice that the traditional
set of six vij~naana amounts to 'representations' because this system uses the convertible
terminology cittamaatra, vij~naanamaatra,and vij~naptimaatra. Five of the six are
representations of the five sense organs (called the 'body'), while the sixth one is a
representation of the sixth sense, manas.
Now we can compare with the four kinds of error of Buddhist logic.
Dharmottara's commentary on Dharmakiirti's Nyaayabindu, following Dharmakiirti's
Pramaa.na-vini'scaya, listed four causes of error.
They are: (1) cause of error found in the object, for example the
whirling firebrand taken as a wheel; (2) cause of error found in a place, for example
embarking in a boat, where the trees on the shore are moving; (3) cause of error found
within, for example being troubled by hatred; and (4) cause of error found in a sense
organ, such as the 'caul', causing the conch shell to appear yellow.(77) It is reasonable
to compare with these four causes of error even though two are placed externally since we
have shown above that Vasubandhu does not deny externals as being existent, provided they
arise in dependence on another.
Number 1, cause of error found in the object, amounts to
representations based on the sixth sense organ, manas. Number 2, cause of error found in a
place, also amounts to representations based on the sixth sense organ, manas. Thus, for
numbers 1 and 2, the representations are called anovij~naana. Skipping to number 4, cause
of error found in a sense organ, the representations are the five outer-directed
perceptions. Notice that this illustration of a caul on the eyes is precisely the example
used by Vasubandhu in the introductory verse to his treatise with twenty verses (above,
subsection "The Theory that Vasubandhu Denies the External World").
Now, going to number 3, the cause of error found within, with the
example of hatred, this clearly goes with representations of the 'defiled mind'. About the
'defiled mind', Asa^nga's Paramaartha-gaathaa, 39-41, contains these points: "The
defiled mind (kli.s.ta.m manas) always arises and ceases together with defilements
(kle'sa)"; "On another occasion it is born pure"; and "That which was
defiled, here in the end is purified, with its intrinsic light
prak.rtibhaasvara)."(78) This shows that the 'defiled mind' requires defilements,
which are dharmas.
Hence, the four causes of error found in those texts of Buddhist logic
are reasonably based on the Yogaacaara theory of 'representation only', and this is
certainly a better solution than my old attempt in the Bhandarkar journal to associate
these four causes of error with the four pratyak.sa of the Buddhist logic system.(79)
Accordingly, these causes of error are not a theory that the world is an illusion, since
the causes of error can be 'seen through', appreciated for what they are, in particular.
Clarification in Terms of Western Discourse.
Modern Western philosophers have concerned themselves with getting
proper descriptive statements regarding perception and its associate functions. Since such
topics can generate much writing, shall restrict my comparisons to issues raised in an
article by Bijoy H. Boruah, "Seeing in the Mind's Eye."(80) He concerned himself
with theories of the author Gilbert Ryle and others. He was clearly impressed with the
phraseology by Elizabeth Anscombe, 'intentional seeing' and 'material seeing'. The example
was: suppose we look at a painting of Gandhi (the 'material seeing'), and then go away and
ask ourselves, "What did I see?" Then these authors are forced to use the same
expression, namely the translation into English of vij~naptimaatra as
'representation-only', but say 'representational seeing', which is 'intentional seeing',
while Wittgenstein used words like 'seeing as'. But then Boruah has to decide that 'seeing
in the mind's eye' is not representational seeing, and this conclusion forces him to
reject various theories by Ryle and others. Thus, to see in the mind's eye is to have an
image that involves both "doing and achieving" and so is distinguished from
"abstract or purely conceptual contemplation." But Boruah recognized (speaking
'metaphorically') that this image "emerges only when the finger of thought touches
the right cord of sentience." He thus admits that a sentience precedes this image.
Asa^nga or it might have been the opponent was cited above for a
consistent remark, which I would now render: "Besides, there is no particular fault
in understanding that there is a prior representation."(81) This apparently means,
"At least there is one thing we can agree on there was some kind of prior
representation. "Therefore, for the Yogaacaara theory of the 'store consciousness',
the seeds stored here cannot sprout unless there is a prior 'representation-only'
triggered by sensory input or by the 'defiled mind'. And the sprouting seeds would provide
the images alluded to in Boruah's essay.
To illustrate the independence of the image from sentience as well as
from abstract thought which Buddhism calls 'discursive thought' (vikalpa, etc.), one could
take the example of the composer Beethoven. He first took classes in music, heard Bach,
and so forth, and this was represented in his mind, 'heard as'. Later, he composed great
works of music, but this did not involve hearing with his ear because he was becoming
stone deaf. Therefore, his auditory imagery of music became independent of sentience, that
is, in terms of hearing external sounds, and was also independent of discursive thought.
He did have discursive thought to change his score "I should change it thus" or
to fume against other persons, and so forth, which is outside his composing music. Of
course, even in his deafness he still had visual input from musical scores.
The example of Beethoven also illustrates the description of the image
here auditory imagery (heard by the sixth sense, manas) as a sort of doing and achieving.
The Yogaacaara issuance from the 'store consciousness' that is expressed in thelanguage of
'seeds' (biija) amounts to a compatible way of talking because the seed can do something,
achieve a result, say, a shoot. Since this issuance from the 'store consciousness' can be
of the indeterminate as well as of the virtuous and the unvirtuous, there are a vast
number of images possible. Since these images can also be called representations, this
shows the active nature of these representations.
It is hoped that this essay, including the preceding three
clarifications, may help to elucidate Yogaacaara Buddhism.
Final Declaration
I hope that the Yogaacaara system has been somewhat clarified on behalf
of anyone who wants it clarified. The misrepresentations of this system that have appeared
in older as well as in recently published works are not more correct simply by being
copied over and over. Of course, the Yogaacaara put its trust in the subjective search for
truth by way of a samaadhi. This rendered the external world not less real, but less
valuable as the way of finding truth.
The tide of misinformation on this, or on any other topic of Indian
lore comes about because authors frequently read just a few verses or
paragraphs of a text, then go to secondary sources, or to treatises by
rivals, and presume to speak authoritatively. Only after doing genuine research on such a
topic can one begin to answer the question: why were those texts and why do the moderns
write the way they do?
Decades ago I knew that the Yogaacaara position was misrepresented in
many works, ancient and modern. Only recently was the means to defend Yogaacaara Buddhism
put in my hands, as has been detailed above. I do not care whether or not others are
convinced by the arguments presented here.
NOTES
1 - Cf. Gregory J. Darling, An Evaluation of the Vedaantic Critique of
Buddhism (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987), p. 371, taking notice of an incorrect
portrayal of Buddhism in Vedaantic criticism.
2 - A. Wayman, "The Yogaacaara Idealism," Philosophy East and
West 15(1)(1965): 65-73.
3 - T.R.V. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism (London: George
Allen and Unwin Ltd., 1955),chap. 13, "The Maadhyamika, Vij~naanavaada and Vedaanta
Absolutism," pp. 311-328.
4 - Lambert Schmithausen, AAlayavij~naana: On the Origin and the Early
Development of a Central Concept of Yogaacaara Philosophy, pt. 1, Text; pt. 2, Notes,
Bibliography and Indices (Tokyo: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies, 1987),
here, pt. 1, pp. 13-14.
5 - Alex Wayman, Analysis of the 'Sraavakabhuumi Manuscript, University
of California Publications in Classical Philology, vol. 17 (Berkeley, California, 1961).
6 - Alex Wayman, review of Hidenori S. Sakuma, Die
AA'srayapariv.rttitheorie in der Yogaacaarabhuumi..., 2 vols. (Stuttgart: Franz Steiner
Verlag, 1990), in Journal of the American Oriental Society 113 (1) (1993): 144.
7 - Bhikkhu ~Naa.nananda, The Magic of the Mind: An Exposition of the
Kaalakaaraama Sutta (Kandy, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society, 1974), pp. 1-92.
8 - F. L. Woodward, The Book of the Gradual Sayings, vol. 2 (London:
Paali Text Society, 1952), pp. 26-28.
9 - William G. Doty, "Hermes' Heteronymous Appellations," in
James Hillman, ed., Facing the Gods (Dallas, Texas: Spring Publications, 1984), p. 131.
10 - See Lozang Jamspal, ed., Abhidhaanavi'svalocanam of 'Sriidharasena
(Narita: Naritasan Shinshoji, 1992); and see Alex Wayman, trans., Abhidhaanavi'svalocanam
of 'Sriidharasena (Narita: Naritasan Shinshoji, 1994).
11 - Alex Wayman, "Doctrinal Affiliation of the Buddhist Master
Asa^nga," in N. H. Samtani, ed., Amalaa Praj~naa: Aspect of Buddhist Studies (Delhi:
Sri Satguru Publications, 1989), p. 214 and n. 74, furnishing the Tibetan in transcription
for the passage.
12 - See, e.g., Th. Stcherbatsky, The Central Conception of Buddhism
and the Meaning of the Word "Dharma" (Calcutta: Susil Gupta, 1961), p.7:
"Consciousness, it is stated, never arises alone, since it is pure sensation, without
any content."
13 - For this simile, see I. B. Horner, trans., The Collection of the
Middle Length Sayings (London: Luzac, 1967), vol. 1, Mahaavedalla-sutta, p. 355, where, in
the case of a burning oil lamp, "the light is seen because of the flame and the flame
is seen because of the light."
14 - This translation is in the 'Sata-Pi.taka series, Indo-Asian
Literatures, vol. 74, published by the International Academy of Indian Culture, New Delhi,
1968; and the passage is at p. 189, where the translator also offers: "What belongs
to the triple world, that is (of) mere mind."
15 - Sylvain Levi, Materiaux pour I'Etude du systeme Vij~naaptimaatra
(Paris: Librairie Ancienne Honore Champion, 1932), p. 13.
16 - When the Japanese scholar, Professor Ryuushin Ohminami, was at
Columbia University some years ago studying this scripture with the Vasubandhu commentary
for a work in Japanese, he kindly gave me both the Peking Tibetan Tanjur edition (PTT) and
the Derge Tibetan edition for Vasubandhu's commentary. I have read the beginning of the
Peking edition, but for the present topic have used just the Derge edition (published by
Delhi Karmapae Chodhey and printed at Mujeeb Press, 1976), the part I discuss at pp. 200
and 202.
17 - As for the terminological set of three, as in Vasubandhu's
Abhidharmako'sa, chap. 2, k. 34a-b, cf. Louis de La Vallee Poussin (Paris,1923), p. 177,
where the autocommentary explains, "Citta is so named because it accumulates
(cinoti); named manas because it knows (manute); named vij~naana because it distinguishes
its object (aalambana.m vijaanaati).
18 - Cf. the Peking Tibetan canon (Japanese photo edition, PTT), vol.
98, p. 127.5-1, citing, "khams gsum po 'di ni rnam par 'ses pa tsam mo"where
rnam par 'ses pa tsam movij~naanamaatra, and is asserted to be these three worlds.
19 - Wayman, Abhidhaanavi'svalocanam of 'Sriidharasena, p.192.
20 - Cf. Louis de La Vallee Poussin, L'Abhidharmako'sa de Vasubandhu:
Troisieme Chapitre (Paris: Paul Geuthner, 1926).
21 - Cf. T. W. and C.A.F. Rhys Davids, Dialogues of the Buddha, pt. 3
(London: Luzac, 1957), pp.77-94.
22 - For three lexicons which include the definition aalambana,
Anundoram Borooah, Naanaarthasa.mgraha (Gauhati: Publication
Board, Assam, 1969), text, p. 3, under "Agra,"cites the
Mediniiko'sa, the Vi'svaprakaa'sa, and the one by Hemacandra. For the fourth one,
see Jamspal, Abhidhaanavi'svalocana, p. 278, no. 1625A. Besides,
aalambana is a definition for agra in these two lexicons of the Deccan
College, Poona, series: Naanaarthama~njarii, by Raaghava, ed. K.R.V.
Sharma (1954), and Dhara.niko'sa by Dhara.nidaasa, ed. E. D.
Kulkarni(1968). The translation by A. Wayman, Ethics of Tibet:
Bodhisattva section of Tsong-kha-pa's Lam rim chen mo (Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1991), adopted the rendering 'area' for
the term agra, as though an area in the mind for meditation.
23 - That is, while preparing my Analysis of the 'Sraavakabhuumi
Manuscript (cited note 5 above).
24 - de La Vallee Poussin, trans. of the Abhidharmako'sa, chap. 1, p.
52.
25 - See Borooah, Naanaarthasa.mgraha; definitions from Mediniiko'sa
and from Vi'svaprakaa'sa. The same in Jamspal, bhidhaanavi'svalocana,
p. 297, no. 1742.
26 - Tsewang, "The Mentalism of Dignaaga and Dharmakiirti,"
in Doboom Tulku, ed., Mind Only School and Buddhist Logic: A Collection of Seminar Papers
(New Delhi: Tibet House and Aditya Prakashan, 1990), p. 15.
27 - See Andre Bareau, "Abhidharmako'sakaarikaa of Vasubandhu:
Index," reprinted from VAAK(Poona: Deccan College), no. 3:45-83.
28 - Clarence H. Hamilton, trans., Wei Shih Er Shih Lun, or The
Treatise in Twenty Stanzas on Representation-Only (New Haven: American Oriental Society,
1938).
29 - Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan and Charles A. Moore, A Source Book in
Indian Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957), pp. 328-333.
30 - Sylvain Levi, Vij~naptimaatrataasiddhi (Paris, 1925; reprint
Shanghai, 1940).
31 - Hamilton, Wei Shih Er Shih Lun, p. 61.
32 - Ibid., n. 114.
33 - The story is cited in F. D. Lessing and A. Wayman, trans.,
Introduction to the Buddhist Tantric Systems (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass,1978), p. 65.
34- Thomas A. Kochumuttom, A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1982), p. 1, contends that the Yogaacaara is really a "realistic
pluralism" rather than, as it is usually described, an "absolute idealism,"
and so on.
35 - Stefan Anacker, Seven Works of Vasubandhu (Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 1984), p. 159, rejects the theory claimed by some persons to be the purport
of Vasubandhu's Twenty Verses that consciousness unilaterally creates all forms in the
universe.
36 - T.R.V. Murti, The Central Philosophy of Buddhism, p. 319.
37 - Schmithausen, AAlayavij~naana, pt. 1, pp. 18 ff.
38 - Ibid., p. 31.
39 - Ibid., pp. 36-39.
40 - Ibid., pp. 5 ff.
41 - Asa^nga, in his Vini'scaya-sa.mgraha.nii, PTT, vol. 110, p. 235.1.
42 - Ibid., p. 235.2.
43 - Ibid., p. 235.4-6.
44 - Ibid., p. 235.4-8.
45 - Ibid., p. 235.5-2.
46 - The Yogaacaarabhuumi of AAcaarya Asa^nga, ed. Vidhushekhara
Bhattacharya (Calcutta:University of Calcutta, 1957), p. 24.4-5.
47 - Ibid., p. 24.18-19.
48 - Vasubandhu, Pratiityasamutpaadaadi-vibha^nganirde'sa, PTT, vol.
104, p. 287.3-3, 4: / de bas na 'du byed kyi rkyen gyis zhing mtshams sbyor ba'i rnam par
'ses pa yin par rigs pa ma yin gyi / ... rnam par 'ses pa ni 'du byed kyi rkyen gyis yin
no / de'i rkyen gyis nying mtshams sbyor
ba'i tshe ming dang gzugs yin no zhes bya ba de lta bu'i lugs 'di ni
skyon med pa yin no /
49 - Gu.namad, Pratiityasamutpaadaadi-vibha^nganirde'satiikaa PTT, vol.
104, p.335-4-2: / chos mngon mdzod las / mtshams sbyor phung po'i rnam par 'ses zhes smras
pa.
50- P. Pradhan, ed., Abhidharmako'sabhaa.syam of Vasubandhu (Patna: K.
P. Jayaswal Research Institute, 1975), p. 124.
51 - Visuddhimagga of Buddhaghosaacariya, ed. Henry Clarke Warren,
revised by Dharmananda Kosambi (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1950), p.477, par.
187.
52 - Bhattacharya, The Yogaacaarabhuumi of AAcaarya Asa^nga, p.26.
18-19.
53 - Ibid., p. 25.13-14.
54 - Ibid., p. 109.13-15.
55 - Vasubandhu, in Derge edition of Tibetan Tanjur, Sems tsam, vol.
Ri, f. 135a-5, 6: / de yang nyon mongs pa can gyi yid kyi rnam par 'ses pa
skye ba'i srid pa la dmigs nas bar ma do'i srid pa 'gag par 'gyur ro /
brgyal ba de la zhes bya ba ni yid kyi rnam par 'ses pa khu ba dang khrag dang lhan cig
grub pa dang / bde ba gcig par 'gyur ba ste / yid kyi rnam par 'ses brgyal par gyur pa de
la brten nas yid kyi rnam par 'ses pa gzhan nyid 'jug par 'gyur ro /
56 - Vasubandhu, Derge, Sems tsam, Ri, f. 69a-5,6: / de'i phyir rnam
par 'ses brgyal ba gang yin pa de ni yid kyi rnam par 'ses pa ma yin gyi / de
ni rnam par smin pa'i rnam par 'ses pa ste desa bon thams cad pa'o /
57 - Gu.namati, Pratiityasamutpaadaadi-vibha^nganirde'satiikaa PTT,
vol.104, p.337.3-3:/ rnam par 'ses pa'i tshogs drug go zhes gsungs kyang yid kyi rnam par
'ses pa kho nas nying mtshams sbrel ba yin pa.
58 - Asa^nga alludes to this in the Yogaacaarabhuumi early section, in
Bhattacharya, The Yogaacaarabhuumi of AAcaarya Asa^nga, p. 25.1-2.
59 - Buddhist Insight: Essays by Alex Wayman, ed. George R. Elder
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1984), p. 330.
60 - Ibid., p. 330.
61 - Gadjin M. Nagao, Maadhyamika and Yogaacaara, trans. Leslie S.
Kawamura (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1991), chap. 6, pp. 61-74.
62 - Ibid., p. 62.
63 - Ibid., p. 70.
64 - Among the editions, there is one in Chr. Lindtner, Nagarjuniana
(Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1987), and another in Fernanda Tola and Carmen Dragonetti,
"Naagaarjuna's Catustava,"Journal of Indian Philosophy 13 (1985).
65 - See the essay by M. A. Mehendale, "Etymology of the Word
Artha-," in his Nirukta Notes, series 1 (Poona: Deccan College, 1965), pp. 42-46.
66 - Bimal Krishna Matilal, Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986),
p. 189.
67 - Chakravarthi Ram Prasad, "Dreams and Reality: The 'Sa^nkarite
Critique of Vij~naana-vaada," Philosophy East and West 43 (3) (July 1993): 405-455.
68 - Kochumuttom, A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience, p. 93.
69 - Cf. F. Th. Stcherbatsky, Buddhist Logic (reprint, New York: Dover
Publications), 1:29.
70 - Alex Wayman, in Journal of the International Association of
Buddhist studies 2 (1) (1979): 65-78.
71 - Alex Wayman, in Annals, Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute
(Diamond Jubilee Volume), 1977-1978, pp. 387-396.
72 - Alex Wayman, in Ernst Steinkellner, ed., Studies in the Buddhist
Epistemological Tradition: Proceedings of the Second International
Dharmakiirti Conference, Vienna, June 11-16, 1989(Wien: Verlag der
Osterreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1991), pp. 419-430.
73 - Tripathi, The Problem of Knowledge...(Varanasi: Bharat-Bharati,
1972), p. 333.
74 - Ibid., pp. 150-151.
75 - Vasubandhu, Derge, Sems tsam, vol. Ri, f.143b-4: / lus dang/ lus
can dang / za ba po'i rnam par rig pa zhes bya ba de la / lus ni mig
la sogs pa'i khams lnga'o / lus can ni nyon mong pa can gyi yid do/ za
ba po ni yid kyi khams so /
76 - Ibid., vol. 'Si, f. 141b-3: / sems ni rnam pa gnyis te / de la
gcig ni de'i sa bon rnams bsag pa yin no / gnyis pa ni de'i dmigs pa dang / rnampa dang /
bye brag tha dad pa dag gis sna tshogs pa yin no /
77 - Wayman, in Annals, Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, pp.
393-394.
78 - Alex Wayman, Analysis of the 'Sraavakabhuumi Manuscript, p. 173;
reprinted in Elder, Buddhist Insight, p. 340.
79 - Wayman, Annals, Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute.
80 - Boruah's essay appeared in Journal of Indian Council of
Philosophical Research 6 (3) (May-August 1989): 119-130.
81 - Since this remark is important, I should cite the Tibetan (alluded to in note 11
above): / rnam par rig pa sngon 'gro ba nyid du rtogs pa'ang de lta na nyes pa khyad par
med pa kho nar 'gyur ro /